文档库 最新最全的文档下载
当前位置:文档库 › 哈佛大学公开课Justice-What's the right thing to do 07

哈佛大学公开课Justice-What's the right thing to do 07

哈佛大学公开课Justice-What's the right thing to do 07
哈佛大学公开课Justice-What's the right thing to do 07

Justice 07 A Lesson in Lying / A Deal is a Deal

Funding for this program is provided by Additional funding provided by Last time we began trying to we began by trying to navigate our way through Kant's moral theory.

Now, fully to make sense of Kant moral theory in the groundwork requires that we be able to answer three questions.

How can duty and autonomy go together?

What's the great dignity in answering to duty?

It would seem that these two ideas are opposed duty and autonomy.

What's Kant's answer to that?

Need someone here to speak up on Kant's behalf.

Does he have an answer?

Yes, go ahead, stand up.

Kant believes you the only act autonomously when you are pursuing something only the name of duty and not because of your own circumstances such as ?C like you're only doing something good and moral if you're doing it because of duty and not because something of your own personal gain.

Now why is that acting°≠what's your name?

My name is Matt.

Matt, why is that acting on a freedom?

I hear what you're saying about duty?

Because you choose to accept those moral laws in yourself and not brought on from outside upon onto you.

Okay, good.

Because acting out of duty ?C Yeah.- is following a moral law That you impose on yourself.

That you impose on yourself.

That's what makes duty compatible with freedom.- Yeah.

Okay, that's good Matt.

That is Kant's answer. That's great.

Thank you. So, Kant's answer is it is not in so far as I am subject to the law that I have dignity but rather in so far as with regard to that very same law, I'm the author and I am subordinated to that law on that ground that I took it as much as at I took it upon myself.

I willed that law.

So that's why for Kant acting according to duty and acting freely in the sense of autonomously are one and the same.

But that raises the question, how many moral laws are there?

Because if dignity consists and be governed by a law that I give myself, what's to guarantee that my conscience will be the same as your conscience?

Who has Kant's answer to that? Yes?

Because a moral law trend is not contingent upon seductive conditions.

It would transcend all particular differences between people and so would be a universal law and in this respect there'd only be one moral law because it would be supreme.

Right. That's exactly right.

What's your name?

Kelly.

Kelly. So Kelly, Kant believes that if we choose freely out of our own consciences, the moral law we're guarantee to come up with one and the same moral law. -Yes.

And that's because when I choose it's not me, Michael Sandel choosing.

It's not you, Kelly choosing for yourself?

What is it exactly?

Who is doing the choosing?

Who's the subject? Who is the agent?

Who is doing the choosing?

Reason? - Well reason°≠Pure reason.

Pure reason and what you mean by pure reason is what exactly?

Well pure reason is like we were saying before not subject to any external conditions that may be imposed on that side.

Good that's' great.

So, the reason that does the willing, the reason that governs my will when I will the moral law is the same reason that operates when you choose the moral law for yourself and that's why it's possible to act autonomously to choose for myself, for each of us to choose for ourselves as autonomous beings and for all of us to wind up willing the same moral law, the categorical imperative.

But then there is one big and very difficult question left even if you accept everything that Matt and Kelly had said so far.

How is a categorical imperative possible?

How is morality possible?

To answer that question, Kant said we need to make a distinction.

We need to make a distinction between two standpoints, two standpoints from which we can make sense of our experience.

Let me try to explain what he means by these two standpoints.

As an object of experience, I belong to the sensible world.

There my actions are determined by the laws of nature and by the regularities of cause and effect.

But as a subject of experience, I inhabit an intelligible world here being independent of the laws of nature I am capable of autonomy, capable of acting according to a law I give myself.

Now Kant says that, "Only from this second standpoint can I regard myself as free for to be independent of determination by causes in the sensible world is to be free." If I were holy and empirical being as the utilitarian assume, if I were a being holy and only subject to the deliverances of my senses, to pain and pleasure and hunger and thirst and appetite, if that's all there were to humanity, we wouldn't be capable of freedom, Kant reasons because in that case every exercise of will would be conditioned by the desire for some object.

In that case all choice would be heteronomous choice governed by the pursued of some external end."When we think of ourselves as free," Kant writes, "we transfer ourselves into the intelligible world as members and recognize the autonomy of the will." That's the idea of the two standpoints.

So how are categorical imperatives possible?

Only because the idea of freedom makes me a member of an intelligible world?

Now Kant admits we aren't only rational beings.

We don't only inhabit the intelligible world, the realm of freedom.

If we did -- if we did, then all of our actions would invariably accord with the autonomy of the will.

But precisely because we inhabit simultaneously the two standpoints, the two realms, the realm of freedom and the realm of necessity precisely because we inhabit both realms there is always potentially a gap between what we do and what we ought to do between is and ought.

Another way of putting this point and this is the point with which Kant concludes the groundwork, morality is not empirical.

Whatever you see in the world, whatever you discover through science can't decide moral questions.

Morality stands at a certain distance from the world, from the empirical world.

And that's why no science could deliver moral truth.

Now I want to test Kant's moral theory with the hardest possible case, a case that he raises, the case of the murderer at the door.

Kant says that lying is wrong.

We all know that.

We've discussed why. Lying is at odds with the categorical imperative.

A French Philosopher, Benjamin Constant wrote an article responding to the groundwork where he said, "This absolute probation online What if a murderer came to your door looking for your friend who was hiding in your house?

And the murderer asked you point blank, "Is your friend in your house?" Constant says, "It would be crazy to say that the moral thing to do in that case is to tell the truth." Constant says the murderer certainly doesn't deserve the truth and Kant wrote to reply.

And Kant stuck by his principle that lying even to the murderer at the door is wrong.

And the reason it's wrong, he said is once you start taking consequences into account to carve out exceptions to the categorical imperative, you've given up the whole moral framework.

You've become a consequentialist or maybe a rule utilitarian.

But most of you and most to our Kant's readers think there's something odd and impossible about this answer.

I would like to try to defend Kant on this point and then I want to see whether you think that my defense is plausible, and I would want to defend him within the spirit of his own account of morality.

Imagine that someone comes to your door.

You were asked that question by this murder.

You are hiding your friend.

Is there a way that you could avoid telling a lie without selling out your friend?

Does anyone have an idea of how you might be able to do that?

Yes? Stand up.

I was just going to say if I were to let my friend in my house to hide in the first place, I'd probably make a plan with them so I'd be like, "Hey I'll tell the murderer you're here, but escape," and that's one of the options mentioned.

But I'm not sure that's a Kantian option.

You're still lying though.

No because he's in the house but he won't be.

Oh I see. All right, good enough.

One more try.

If you just say you don't know where he is because he might not be locked in the closet.

He might have left the closet.

You have no clue where he could be.

So you would say, I don't know which wouldn't actually be a lie because you weren't at that very moment looking in the closet.

Exactly.-So it would be strictly speaking true.

Yes.

And yet possibly deceiving, misleading.-But still true.

What's your name?-John.

John. All right, John has...now John may be on to something.

John you're really offering us the option of a clever evasion that is strictly speaking true. This raises the question whether there is a moral difference between an outright lie and a misleading truth.

From Kant's point of view there actually is a world of difference between a lie and a misleading truth.

Why is that even though both might have the same consequences?

But then remember Kant doesn't base morality on consequences.

He bases it on formal adherence to the moral law.

Now, sometimes in ordinary life we make exceptions for the general rule against lying with the white lie.

What is a white lie?

It's a lie to make...you're well to avoid hurting someone's feelings for example.

It's a lie that we think of as justified by the consequences.

Now Kant could not endorse a white lie but perhaps he could endorse a misleading truth. Supposed someone gives you a tie, as a gift, and you open the box and it's just awful. What do you say? Thank you.

You could say thank you.

But they're waiting to see what you think of it or they ask you what do you think of it?

You could tell a white lie and say it's beautiful.

But that wouldn't be permissible from Kant's point of view.

Could you say not a white lie but a misleading truth, you open the box and you say, "I've never seen a tie like that before.

Thank you." You shouldn't have.

That's good.

Can you think of a contemporary political leader who engaged...you can?

Who are you thinking of?

You remember the whole carefully worded denials in the Monica Lewinsky affair of Bill Clinton.

Now, those denials actually became the subject of very explicit debate in argument during the impeachment hearings.

Take a look at the following excerpts from Bill Clinton.

Is there something do you think morally at stake in the distinction between a lie and a misleading carefully couched truth?

I want to say one thing to the American people.

I want you to listen to me.

I'm going to say this again.

I did not have sexual relations with that woman Miss Lewinsky.

I never told anybody to lie not a single time, never. These allegations are false.

Did he lie to the American people when he said I never had sex with that woman?

You know, he doesn't believe he did and because of the °≠Well he didn't explain it.

He did explain that, explain congressman.

What he said was to the American people that he did not have sexual relations and I understand you're not going to like this congressman because you will see it as a hair-splitting evasive answer.

But in his own mind his definition was not...

Okay, I understand that argument.-Okay.

All right, so there you have the exchange.

Now at the time, you may have thought this was just a legalistic hair-splitting exchange between a Republican who wanted to impeach Clinton and a lawyer who is trying to defend him.

But now in the light of Kant, do you think there is something morally at stake in the distinction between a lie and an evasion, a true but misleading statement?

I'd like to hear from defenders of Kant.

People who think there is a distinction.

Are you ready to defend Kant?

Well I think when you try to say that lying and misleading truths are the same thing; you're basing it on consequentialist argument which is that they achieve the same thing.

But the fact to the fact to the matter is you told the truth and you intended that people would

believe what you are saying which was the truth which means it is not morally the same as telling a lie and intending that they believe it is the truth even though it is not true.

Good. What's your name?-Diana.

So Diana says that Kant has a point here and it's a point that might even come to the aid of Bill Clinton and that is °≠well what about that?

There's someone over here.

For Kant motivation is key, so if you give to someone because primarily you want to feel good about yourself Kant would say that has no moral worth.

Well with this, the motivation is the same.

It's to sort of mislead someone, it's to lie, it's to sort of throw them off the track and the motivation is the same.

So there should be no difference.

Okay, good. So here isn't the motive the same Diana?

What do you say to this argument that well the motive is the same in both cases there is the attempt or at least the hope that one's pursuer will be misled?

Well that ?C you could look it that way but I think that the fact is that your immediate motive is that they should believe you.

The ultimate consequence of that is t hat they might be deceived and not find out what was going on.

But that your immediate motive is that they should believe you because you're telling the truth.

May I help a little?-Sure.

You and Kant. Why don't you say...and what's your name, I'm sorry?

Wesley.

Why don't you say to Wesley it's not exactly the case that the motive in both cases is to mislead?

They're hoping, they're hoping that the person will be misled by the statement "I don't know where they are" or "I never had sexual relations." You're hoping that they will be misled but in the case where you're telling the truth, you're motive is to mislead while at the same time telling the truth and honoring the moral law and staying within the bounds of the categorical imperative.

I think Kant's answer would be Diana, yes?-Yes.

You like that?-I do.

Okay. So I think Kant's answer would be unlike a falsehood, unlike a lie, a misleading truth pays a certain homage to duty.

And the homage it pays to duty is what justifies that the work of even the work of the evasion.

And so there is something, some element of respect for the dignity of the moral law in the careful evasion because Clinton could have told an outright lie but he didn't.

And so I think Kant's insight here is in the carefully couched but true evasion.

There is a kind of homage to the dignity of the moral law that is not present in the outright lie and that, Wesley, is part of the motive.

It's part of the motive.

Yes, I hope he will be misled.

I hope the murderer will run down the road or go to the mall looking for my friend instead at the closet.

I hope that will be the effect.

I can't control that.

I can't control the consequences.

But what I can control is standing by and honoring however I pursue the ends, I hope will unfold to do so in a way that is consistent with respect for the moral law.

Wesley, I don't think, is entirely persuaded but at least this brings out, this discussion brings out some of what it's at stake, what's morally at stake in Kant's notion of the categorical imperative.

As long as any effort this involved I would say that the contract is valid then.

It should take effect.

But why? What was...what morally can you point to?

For example two people agreed to be married and one suddenly called the other in two minutes say I changed my mind.

Does the contract have obligation on both sides?

Well I am tempted to say no.

Fine.

Last time we talked about Kant's categorical imperative and we considered the way he applied the idea of the categorical imperative to the case of lying.

I want to turn briefly to one other application of Kant's moral theory and that's his political theory.

Now Kant says that just laws arise from a certain kind of social contract.

But this contract he tells us is of an exceptional nature.

What makes the contract exceptional is that it is not an actual contract that happens when people come together and try to figure out what the constitution should be.

It's not an actual contract among actual men and women gathered in a constitutional convention.

Why not?

I think Kant's reason is that actual men and women gathered in real constitutional convention would have different interests, values, aims, and it would also be differences of bargaining power and differences of knowledge among them.

And so the laws that would result from their deliberations wouldn't necessarily be just, wouldn't necessarily conform to principles of right but would simply reflect the differences a bargaining power, the special interests the fact that some might know more than others about law or about politics.

So Kant says, "A contract that generates principles of right is merely an idea of reason but it has undoubted practical reality because it can oblige every legislator to frame his laws in such a way that they could have been produced by the united will of the whole nation." So Kant is a contractarian, but he doesn't trace the origin or the rightness of law to any actual social contract.

This contrives to an obvious question.

What is the moral force of a hypothetical contract, a contract that never happened?

That's the question we take up today but in order to investigate it, we need to turn to a modern philosopher, John Rawls, who worked out in his book, A Theory of Justice, in great detail and account of a hypothetical agreement as the basis for justice.

Rawls' theory of justice in broad outline is parallel to Kant's in two important respects.

Like Kant, Rawls was a critic of utilitarianism."Each person possesses an inviolability founded on justice," Rawls' writes, "that even the welfare of society as a whole cannot override.

The rights secured by justice are not subject to political bargaining or to the calculus social interests." The second respect in which Rawls' theory follows Kant's is on the idea that principles of justice properly understood can be derived from a hypothetical social contract. Not an actual one.

And Rawls works this out in fascinating detail with the device of what he calls the "veil of ignorance".

The way to arrive at the rights...the basic rights that we must respect, the basic framework of rights and duties is to imagine that we were gathered together trying to choose the principles to govern our collective lives without knowing certain important particular fact about ourselves.

That's the idea of the veil of ignorance.

Now what would happen if we gather together just as we are here and try to come up with principles of justice to govern our collective life?

There would be a cacophony of proposals of suggestions reflecting people's different interests, some are strong, some are weak, some are rich, some are poor.

what assures the equality is the veil of ignorance.

Imagine that we are all behind a veil of ignorance which temporarily abstracts from or brackets, hides from us who in particular we are.

Our race, our class, our place in society, our strengths, our weaknesses, whether we're healthy or unhealthy, then and only then Rawls says, the principles we would agree to would be principles of justice.

That's how the hypothetical contract works.

What is the moral force of this kind of hypothetical agreement?

Is it stronger or weaker than a real agreement, an actual social contract?

In order to answer that question, we have to look hard at the moral force of actual contracts.

There are really two questions here.

One of them is how do actual contracts bind me or obligate me?

Question number one.

And question number two, how do actual real life contracts justify the terms that they produce?

If you think about it and this is in line with Rawls and Kant, the answer to the second question, how do actual contracts justify the terms that they produce, the answer is they don't.

At least not on their own.

Actual contracts are not self-sufficient moral instruments of any actual contract or agreement.

It can always be asked, is it fair what they agreed to?

The fact of the agreement never guarantees the fairness of the agreement and we know this by looking at our own constitutional convention.

It produced a constitution that permitted slavery to persist.

It was agreed to.

It was an actual contract but that doesn't establish that the laws agreed to all of them were just.

Well then what is the moral force of actual contracts?

To the extent that they bind us, they obligate in two ways.

Suppose, maybe here it would help to take an example.

We make an agreement, a commercial agreement.

I promise to pay you $100 if you will go harvest and bring to me 100 lobsters.

You go out and harvest them and bring them to me.

I eat the lobsters, served them to my friends, and then I don't pay.

And you say, "But you're obligated." And I say, "Why?" What do you say? "Well we had a deal." And you benefited.

You ate all those lobsters.

Well that's a pretty strong argument.

It's an argument that depends though and the fact that I benefited from your labor So, contracts sometimes bind us in so far as they are instruments of mutual benefit.

I ate the lobsters. I owe you the $100 for having gathered them.

But suppose, now take a second case.

We make this deal, I'll pay you $100 for 380 before you've gone to any work I call you back and say I've changed my mind.

Now, there's no benefit.

There's no work on your part so there's no element of reciprocal exchange.

What about in that case, do I still owe you merely in virtue of the fact that we had an agreement?

Who says those of you who say, yes, I still owe you? Why? Okay, stand up.

Why do I owe you?

I called you back after two minutes.

You haven't done any work.

I think I spent the time and effort in drafting this contract with you and also have emotional expectation that I go through the work.

So you took time to draft the contract but we did it very quickly.

We just chatted on the phone.

That wouldn't be a formal form of contract though.

Well I faxed at you.

It only took a minute.

As long as any effort is involved, I would say that the contract is valid then.

It should take effect.

But why? What was...what morally can you point to that obligates me?

I admit that I agreed but you didn't go to any work. I didn't enjoy any benefit.

Because one might mentally go through all the work of harvesting the lobsters.

You mentally went through the work of harvesting the lobsters.

That's nothing is it?

It's not much.

Is it worth $100 that you were imagining yourself going and collecting lobsters?

It may not worth $100, but it may worth something to some people.

All right, I'll give you a buck for that.

But what I ?C so you're still pointing...what's interesting you're still pointing to the reciprocal dimension of contracts.

You did or imagined that you did or looked forward to doing something that might be had. For example two people agreed to be married and one suddenly calls the other in two minutes say, I've changed my mind, does the contract have obligation on both sides? Nobody has done any work or nobody has benefited yet.

Well I'm tempted to say no.

Fine.

All, right. What's your name?-Julian.

Thank you Julian.

All right, that was good.

Now is there anyone who has who agrees with Julian that I still owe the money?

For any other reason now I have °≠go ahead, stand up.

I think if you back out it sort of cheapens the institution of contracts.

Good but why? Why does it?

Well I think is kind of Kantian, but there's in almost there's a certain intrinsic value in being able to make contracts and having, you know, knowing people will expect that you'll go through with that.

Good, there is some...it would cheapen the whole idea of contracts which has to do with taking in obligation on myself. Is that the idea?

Yeah, I think so.

What's your name?-Adam.

So Adam points instead not to any reciprocal benefit or mutual exchange but to the mere fact of the agreement itself.

We see here there are really two different ways in which actual contracts generate obligations.

One has to do with the active consent as a voluntary act and it points...

Adam said this was a Kantian idea and I think he is right because it points to the ideal of autonomy.

When I make a contract, the obligation is one that is self-imposed and that carries a certain moral weight, independent of other considerations.

And then there's a second element of the moral force of contract arguments which has to do with the sense in which actual contracts are instruments of mutual benefit and this points toward the ideal of reciprocity that obligation can arise, I can have an obligation to you in so far as you do something for me.

Now, when investigating the moral force and also the moral limits of actual contracts and here I would like to advance an argument about the moral limits of actual contracts now that we know what moral ingredients do the work when people come together and say, "I will do this if you do that." I would like to argue first that the fact that two people agreed to some exchange does not mean that the terms of their agreement are fair.

When my two sons were young they collected baseball cards and traded them.

And one was...there was a two-year aged...there is a two-year aged difference between them and so I had to institute a rule about the trades that no trade was complete until I had approved it and the reason is obvious.

The older one knew more about the value of these cards and so would take advantage of the younger one.

So that's why I had to review it to make sure that the agreements were fair.

Now you may say, "Well this is paternalism." Of course it was. That's what paternalism is for that kind of thing.

So what does this show?

What is the baseball cards example show?

The fact of an agreement is not sufficient to establish the fairness of the terms.

I read some years ago of a case in Chicago there was an elderly widow, an 84-year-old widow named Rose who had a problem in her apartment with a leaky toilet and she signed a contract with an unscrupulous contractor, who offered to repair her leaky toilet in exchange for $50,000.

But she had agreed she was of sound mind, maybe terribly naive and unfamiliar with the price of plumbing, she had made this agreement.

Luckily, it was discovered.

She went to the bank and asked to withdraw $25,000.

And the teller said, "Why do you need all of that money for?" And she said, "Well, I have a leaky toilet." And the teller called authorities and they discovered this unscrupulous contractor.

Now, I suspect that even the most ardent contract carryings in the room will agree that the fact of this woman's agreement is not a sufficient condition of the agreement being fair.

Is there anyone who will dispute that?

No one. Am I missing anyone?

Alex, where are you?

Where are you?

So, maybe there's no dispute then to my first claim that an actual agreement is not necessary to their..is not a sufficient condition of there being an obligation.

I want to now make us stronger, maybe more controversial claim about the moral limits of actual contracts that a contract or an active consent is not only not sufficient but it's not even a necessary condition of there being an obligation.

And the idea here is that if there is reciprocity, if there is an exchange, then a receipt of benefits, there can be an obligation even without an act of consent.

One great example of this involves the 18th century philosopher, the Scottish moral philosopher David Hume.

When he was young, Hume wrote a book arguing against Locke's idea of an original social contract.

Hume heaps scorn on his contractarian idea.

He said it was a philosophical fiction.

One of the most mysterious and incomprehensible operations that can possibly be imagined this idea of the social contract.

Many years later when he was 62 years old, Hume had an experience that put to the test his rejection of consent us the basis of obligation.

Hume had a house in Edinboro.

He rented to his friend James Boswell who in turn sublet it to a subtenant.

The subtenant decided that the house needed some repairs and a paint job.

He hired a contractor to do the work.

The painter did the work and sent the bill to Hume.

Hume refused to pay on the grounds that he hadn't consented.

He hadn't hired the painter.

The case went to court.

The contractor said, "It's true, Hume didn't agree but the house needed the painting and I gave it a very good one." Hume thought this was a bad argument.

The only argument this painter makes is that the work was necessary to be done but this is no good answer because by the same rule, this painter may go through every house in

Edinboro and do what he thinks proper to be done without the landlord's consent and give the same reason that the work was necessary and that the house was the better for it.

So Hume didn't like the theory that there could be obligation to repay a benefit without consent. But the defense failed and he had to pay.

Let met give you one other example of the distinction between the consent-based aspect of obligations and the benefit-based aspect and how they're sometimes run together.

This is based on a personal experience.

Some years ago, I was driving across the country with some friends and we found ourselves in the middle of nowhere in Hammond, Indiana.

We stopped in a rest stop and got out of the car and when we came back our car wouldn't start.

None of us knew much about cars.

We didn't really know what to do until we noticed that in the parking lot driving up next to us was a van and on the side it said, "Sam's mobile repair van." And out of the van came a man, presumably Sam and he came up to us and he said, "Can I help you?

Here's how I work.

I work by the hour for $50 an hour.

If I fix your car in five minutes, you owe me the $50 and if I work on your car for an hour and can't fix it, you'll still owe me the $50." So I said, "But what is the likelihood that you'll be able to fix the car" and he didn't answer.

But he did start looking under the poking around the steering column.

Short time passed, he emerged from under the steering column and said, "There's nothing wrong with the ignition system but you still have 45 minutes left.

Should I look under the hood?" I said, "Wait a minute. I haven't hired you.

We haven't made any agreement." And then he became very angry and he said, "Do you mean to say that if I had fixed your car while I was working under the steering column that you wouldn't have paid me?" And I said, "That's a different question." I didn't go into the distinction between consent based and benefit based applications.

But I think he had the intuition that if he had fixed it while he was poking around that I would have owed him the $50.

I shared that intuition. I would have.

But he inferred from that.

This was the fallacy and the reasoning that I think lay behind his anger.

He inferred from that fact that therefore implicitly we had an agreement.

But that it seems to me as a mistake.

It's a mistake that fails to recognize the distinction between these two different aspects of contract arguments.

Yes, I agree. I would have owed him $50 if he had repaired my car during that time not because we had made any agreement.

We hadn't.

But simply because if he had fixed my car, he would have conferred on me a benefit for which I would have owed him in the name of reciprocity and fairness.

So here's another example of the distinction between these two different kinds of arguments, these two different aspects of the morality of contract.

Now I want to hear how many think I was in the right in that case?

That's reassuring. Is there anyone who thinks I was in the wrong?

Anyone? You do?

Why? Go ahead.

Isn't the problem with this is that any benefit is inherently subjectively defined?

I mean what if you wanted your car broken and he had fixed it? I mean...

No, I didn't want it broken.

Yeah in this case. I mean...

But who would?

Who would?

I don't know, someone.

I mean what if Hume, you know, what if the painter that painted his house blue but he hated the color blue, I mean you have to sort of define what your benefit is before the person does it.

Well all right, so what would you conclude for that though for the larger issue here, would you conclude that therefore consent is a necessary condition of their being an obligation? Absolutely.-You would. What's your name?

Nate.

Because otherwise how can we know, Nate says, whether there has been an exchange of equivalent or fair benefits unless we have the subjective evaluation which may vary one person to the next of the situation.

All right, that's a fair challenge.

Let me put to you one other example in order to test the relation between these two aspects of the morality of contract.

Suppose I get married and suppose I discover that after 20 years of faithfulness on my part, every year on our trip across the country my wife has been seeing another man, a man with a van on the Indiana toll road.

This part is completely made up by the way.

Wouldn't I have two different reasons for moral outrage?

One reason could be we had an agreement.

She broke her promise referring to the fact of her consent.

But I would also have a second ground for moral outrage having nothing to do with the contract as such but I've been so faithful for my part.

Surely I deserve better than this.

Is this what I'm doing in return and so on?

So that would point to the element of reciprocity.

Each reason has an independent moral force.

That's the general point and you can see this if you imagine a slight variation on the marriage case.

Suppose we haven't been married for 20 years.

Suppose we were just married and that the betrayal occurred on the way to our honeymoon in Hammond, Indiana.

After the contract has been made, but before there is any history of performance on my part, performance of the contract I mean, I would still with Julian, I'd be able to say but you promised, you promised.

That would isolate the pure element of consent, right where there were no benefits, never mind. You get the idea.

Here's the main idea, actual contracts have their moral force in virtue of two distinguishable ideals: autonomy and reciprocity, but in real life every actual contract may fall short, may fail to realize the ideals that give contracts their moral force in the first place.

The ideal of autonomy may not be realized because there may be a difference in the bargaining power of the parties.

The ideal of reciprocity may not be realized because there may be a difference of knowledge between the parties and so they may misidentify what really counts as having equivalent value.

Now suppose you were to imagine a contract where the ideals of autonomy and of reciprocity were not subject to contingency but were guaranteed to be realized, what kind of contract would that have to be?

Imagine a contract among parties who were equal in power and knowledge rather than unequal who are identically situated rather than differently situated?

That is the idea behind Rawls' claim that the way to think about justice is from the standpoint of a hypothetical contract, behind a veil of ignorance that creates the condition of equality by ruling out or enabling us to forget for the moment the differences in power and knowledge that could even in principle lead to unfair results.

This is why for Kant and for Rawls a hypothetical contract among equals is the only way to

think about principles of justice.

What will those principles be?

That's the question we'll turn to next time.

Don't miss the chance to interact online with other viewers of Justice.

Join the conversation.

Take a pop quiz, watch lectures you've missed and learn a lot more. This is at https://www.wendangku.net/doc/b615100561.html,.

哈佛大学公开课

哈佛大学公开课“幸福课”第四课 大家好,我们是“哈佛召回”组合,想向教员和同学们传达一份特殊的情人节讯息…..(唱歌)。 早上好,请他们献歌时,本来想选另一首歌,但是…算了吧。“我们确实爱你们”。 今天课程的内容是上节课的延续,是这门课的基本前提,“我们来自哪里,我们将去哪里”。从各个方面展开论述螺旋的基础,我们将在本学期一起创建它。上次我们讲到改变有多么困难,我们谈到“双胞胎研究”(Twin studies),Lykken和Tellegen提出的,也许改变我们幸福水平和试图改变身高一样困难和徒劳无功,然后谈到这些研究学者们犯的一般性的失误和错误,误解改变的本质,因为如果一个人在改变,问题已不再是“是否可能改变?”,而是“怎样才可能改变”。还谈到剑桥--萨摩维尔研究(Somerville Cambridge study),证明劳斯莱斯干预彻底失败。五年来,剑桥,哈佛和麻省理工的顶尖科学家,研究人员,精神病专家和心理学家,沥尽心血,带着美好的意图,事实改变,但最终失败。不仅没有实现正面的改变,实际上是带去了负面的改变。还记得吗?干预组的酗酒比例和对照组相比是增加的,未参与干预的对照组更有可能在二三十年后获得升职。改变是困难的,但我们又说“Marva Collins实现了改变,所以改变是可能的”。Martin Seligmen和Karen Reivich及大量学者都成功地实现改变,困难在于如果我们想成为实践理想主义者就是要理解是什么带来改变然后去做。传播理念,传播研究的理念,即使研究并非总是传达好消息,它传达的是行之有效的方法,渴望,希望,愿望,那远远不够。好的意愿,理想主义,好的意图是不够的,我们需要扎根于研究。这正是Maslow的想法,当他谈及类似的曼哈顿计划时,科学家,积极心理学家,当时的心理学家和社学科学工作者聚在一起,在流行学术领域中挑出几种观念,几个有效的项目,再复制它们。研究最好的,正如Mariam同学课后找到我时说的“流行学术其实是要将杰出大众化”,我喜欢这个说法。将杰出大众化研究最好的再应用在其他人身上。我们有了这样一个伟大的计划,有了Maslow创造类似曼哈顿计划(Manhattan-type Project)的伟大想法。但是如果我不想参与计划呢?不想成为学者?只想做自己的事,我能否实现改变?答案是:绝对能够。 人若想在世间有岁作为,真正实现改变,面对的最显著障碍之一是他们低估自己实现改变的能力。心理学界有很多研究。爱默生(Emerson)和莫斯科维奇(Moscovici)是先驱,他们和其他学者都证明少数人,经常是一个人,如何实现重大改变,能实现显著的改变。爱默生说:“人类历史是少数派和一个人的少数派的权力记录”。很多社会科学研究支持这个观点。人类学家Margaret Mead说:“永远不要怀疑一小群有思想、坚定的市民可以改变世界。”事实上,正是这群人改变着世界。所有改变从一个人或一小众人的思想开始,然后不断扩大。问题是“他如何扩大”以及为什么我们难以理解我们能够做出改变这个事实,并接受,被同化以及据此生活。如果我们能了解我们需要理解的是改变如何发生,改变以指数级发生,我们与其他人的联系及他们与更多人的联系形成了一个指数函数,可以用你们熟悉的“蝴蝶效应”(butterfly effect)为例加以解释,一只蝴蝶在新加坡拍动翅膀,理论上能在佛罗里达引起龙卷风,原因在于粒子的连续碰撞。它也解释了六度分隔理论(6 degrees of separation):在一个潜在善的网络里我们是关联和相互关联的。为了说明人类网络的指数本质,我们来以笑为例。研究证明笑有传染性,别人笑会引起你发笑,你笑会引起别人发笑,以此类推。即使路人与你擦肩而过时,你没笑,表面上你没有笑,但你面部的细微肌肉会收缩,让你感觉更好。笑是传染的。如果你的笑感染了三个人,这三个人,每个人又引起另外三人发笑,那九个人,每个人再用笑容感染三个人,只需要20度的分隔,从你用笑容感染三个人开始,全世界就会笑起来。社会网络的指数本质,让别人感觉良好也有感染力。恭维别人,如果你能让三个人,甚至四个人度过美妙的一天,他们会推展,让四人有美好的一天,以此类推。只需要很短的时间,整个世界都会感觉更加美好。这是

哈佛公开课:幸福课 第一集 笔记(April记录)

哈佛公开课:幸福课 Harvard Open Course : Positive Psychology 背景: “幸福课”是2010年哈佛最受欢迎的选修课是,听课人数超过了王牌课《经济学导论》。教这门课的是一位名不见经传的年轻讲师,泰勒?本-沙哈尔。他的课程使得他成了“哈佛红人”。他提出:幸福,是可以通过学习和练习获得的。”他的课程目标在于把艰深的积极心理学学术成果简约化、实用化,让学生懂得自我帮助。 第一课什么是积极心理学 积极心理学课程由来 首先,解释自己为什么想开这门课“因为这是我自己想上的一门课”,然后叙述自己走入积极心理学研究的过程。——当自己刚进入哈佛,一切都仿佛很好,但他却不快乐。于是他想解决这个问题,于是慢慢从计算机走入心理学领域。(好棒的跨度,在国外因为想了解一样东西而跨专业好像蛮common的) 然后介绍了他逐渐从8个人的讨论组到850个人的大课的过程,写到达到850人后,引起了媒体的兴趣,然后描述了媒体采访他的时候,总是提出的一个问题“你比我们想象的更内向”,作为一个joke,1米7不够资格传授快乐吗?(good joke point,并且不光是joke,是发人深思的一种现象)但点出了他最后反思而得:因为他们想给自己一个答案:为什么这个课这样流行,唯一解释就是导师乐观开朗、高大。但他们关注错了,他们应该关注信息,而非传达者。因为这个课程遍及全国,以及全球。(这样引入幸福课的普及,远较直接说XX学校也开了XX好得多) 各个大学开设此课程,各国政府也是,为什么?因为它有效。幸福感这一领域,此前一直被心理自助运动统治,心理自助运动带来什么?热情外向的宣讲者,常具领袖气质,吸引大众参加他们的讲座,但常常言过其实。(通过描述相对立的一种心理学运动来映衬积极心理学) 再来说说学术界——(引入人们对学术界知之甚少,但学术界有好东西,又用了一个比较):有多少人度过最近12期的《个性与社会心理学》?大多数人甚至不知道这是什么东西,我博士班的班主任估计过,学术期刊上一篇文章的读者只有7个人,甚至包括作者的母亲。(用具体的人代替somebody,令人更有亲切感,母亲的joke两个亮点)总结:作为学者,我觉得这很可悲,因为这些研究非常精彩、非常重要,但是晦涩难懂,所以我们需要积极心理学的课程,在象牙塔和大众之间搭建桥梁。(又落脚到主题,本课程的意义)

哈佛公开课-公正课中英字幕_第一课

制作人:心舟 QQ:1129441083 第一讲《杀人的道德侧面》 这是一门讨论公正的课程This is a course about justice 我们以一则故事作为引子and we begin with a story. 假设你是一名电车司机\Suppose you're the driver of a trolley car 你的电车以60英里小时的速度\and your trolley car is hurtling down the track 在轨道上飞驰\at 60 miles an hour. 突然发现在轨道的尽头\And at the end of the track you notice 有五名工人正在施工\five workers working on the track. 你无法让电车停下来\You try to stop but you can't 因为刹车坏了\your brakes don't work. 你此时极度绝望\You feel desperate 因为你深知\because you know 如果电车撞向那五名工人\that if you crash into these five workers 他们全都会死\they will all die. 假设你对此确信无疑\Let's assume you know that for sure. 你极为无助\And so you feel helpless 直到你发现在轨道的右侧until you notice that there is off to the right 有一条侧轨\ a side track 而在侧轨的尽头\and at the end of that track 只有一名工人在那施工\there is one worker working on the track. 而你的方向盘还没坏\Your steering wheel works 只要你想\so you can turn the trolley car 就可以把电车转到侧轨上去\if you want to onto the side track 牺牲一人挽救五人性命\killing the one but sparing the five. 下面是我们的第一个问题:\Here's our first question: 何为正确的选择\what's the right thing to do? 换了你会怎么做\What would you do? 我们来做个调查\Let's take a poll. 有多少人会把电车开到侧轨上去\How many would turn the trolley car onto the side track? 请举手\Raise your hands. 有多少人会让电车继续往前开\How many wouldn't? How many would go straight ahead? 选择往前开的请不要把手放下\Keep your hands up those of you who would go straight ahead. 只有少数人选择往前开\A handful of people would 绝大多数都选择转弯\the vast majority would turn. 我们先来听听大家的说法\Let's hear first 探究一下为何\now we need to begin to investigate the reasons 你们会认为这是正确的选择\why you think it's the right thing to do. 先从大多数选择了转向侧轨的同学开始\Let's begin with those in the majority who

幸福课_哈佛公开课第一课中文字幕

第一课 各位,早上好。很高兴能回到这里。 高兴见到你们。 我教授这门课是因为在我读本科阶段时非常希望能学习这样一门课程。 可能这门课并不是你希望的那样也可能并不适合你。 但希望几堂课后,你能有个大概印象让你决定这门课程是否适合你。 我1992年来到哈佛求学,一开始主修计算机科学。 大二期间,突然顿悟了。 我意识到我身处让人神往大学校园周围都是出色的同学,优秀的导师。 我成绩优异。擅长体育运动。那时壁垒打的不错。社交也游刃有余。 一切都很顺利除了一点我不快乐。而且我不明白为什么。 也就是在那时我决定要找出原因变得快乐。 于是我将研究方向从计算机科学转向了哲学及心理学。 目标只有一个:怎么让自己开心起来。 渐渐的,我的确变得更快乐了主要是因为我接触了一个新的领域,那时并未正式命名。 但本质上属于积极心理学畴。 研究积极心理学把其理念应用到生活中让我无比快乐。 而且这种快乐继续着。 于是我决定将其与更多的人分享。 选择教授这门学科。 这就是积极心理学,1504号心理学课程。 我们将一起探索这一全新相对新兴令人倾倒的领域。 希望同时还能探索我们自己。 我第一次开设这门课程是在2002年。 是以讨论会的形式,只有8名学生。两名退出了只剩我和其他六个人。一年后学生稍微多了点。有300多人参加。到了第三年,也就是上一次开课。 有850名参加是当时哈佛大学人数最多的课程。 这引起了媒体的注意。因为他们想知道为什么。 他们对这一奇特现象非常好奇竟然有比经济学导论更热门的课程。怎么可能呢? 于是我被请去参加各类媒体采访,报纸,广播,电视。 在这些采访中,我发现了一种有趣的模式。 我前去参加采访。进行采访。 结束后,制片人或主持人会送我出来。说些诸如Tal多你抽空参加采访。 不过你跟我想象的不太一样的话。 我漫不经心的问。 我无所谓,不过总得回应“有何不同?” 他们会说“这个嘛,我们会以为你很外向”。 下一次采访结束时仍是如此“多接受采访”。 不过Tal,你跟我想象得不太一样。

哈佛公开课《幸福学》的经典语句

1. When we suppress a natural phenomenon that phenomenon only strengthens 当我们压抑一种自然现象时,那种现象只会加强 2.Painful emotions are as much as part of human nature, as the law of the gravity is part of physical nature 人类本性的痛苦情绪,一如物理世界的万有引力定律 3.Belief as self-fulfilling Prophecies. We creat our reality. 信念即自我实现预言,我们创造我们的现实。 4.We are what we think. All that we are arises with our thoughts.With our thoughts ,we make our world. 境随心转,全由意念升起,我们的念头造就了世界。 5.Goethe,“Treat a man as he is and will remain as he is. Treat a man as he can and should be, and he shall become as he can and should be” 歌德说:“人是怎样便怎样待他,他便还是这样的人.一个人能够或应该怎样便怎样待他,他便会成为能够怎样或是应当怎样的人。” 6.James stockdale said,” You must confuse faith that you would prevail in the end which you can never afford to lose with the discipline to confront the most brutal facts of your current reality whatever you might be .” James stockdale说:“你不能把坚信自己最终会在输不起的情况

哈佛大学公开课《公正:该如何做是好》:全五课:英文字幕

THE MORAL SIDE OF MURDER This is a course about justice and we begin with a story. Suppose you're the driver of a trolley car, and your trolley car is hurtling down the track at 60 miles an hour. And at the end of the track you notice five workers working on the track. You try to stop but you can't, your brakes don't work. You feel desperate because you know that if you crash into these five workers, they will all die. Let's assume you know that for sure. And so you feel helpless until you notice that there is, off to the right, a side track and at the end of that track, there is one worker working on the track. Your steering wheel works, so you can turn the trolley car, if you want to, onto the side track killing the one but sparing the five. Here's our first question: what's the right thing to do? What would you do? Let's take a poll. How many would turn the trolley car onto the side track? Raise your hands. How many wouldn't? How many would go straight ahead? Keep your hands up those of you who would go straight ahead. A handful of people would, the vast majority would turn. Let's hear first, now we need to begin to investigate the reasons why you think it's the right thing to do. Let's begin with those in the majority who would turn to go onto the side track. Why would you do it? What would be your reason? Who's willing to volunteer a reason? Go ahead. Stand up. Because it can't be right to kill five people when you can only kill one person instead. It wouldn't be right to kill five if you could kill one person instead. That's a good reason. That's a good reason. Who else? Does everybody agree with that reason? Go ahead. Well I was thinking it's the same reason on 9/11 with regard to the people who flew the plane into the Pennsylvania field as heroes because they chose to kill the people on the plane and not kill more people in big buildings. So the principle there was the same on 9/11. It's a tragic circumstance but better to kill one so that five can live, is that the reason most of you had, those of you

哈佛大学公开课 –公正 迈克尔

哈佛大学公开课–公正迈克尔.桑德尔教授主讲-<<杀人道德的侧面>> 由Graywolf_Robbie整理 这段时间一直在学习著名大学的公开课程,如哈佛大学的[该如何是好],[幸福课],[心理学],耶鲁大学的[金融市场],[博弈论],[心理学导论][死亡],普林斯顿大学的[领导能力简介],[人性],还有斯坦福大学的[经济学],[商业领袖和企业家].等等,下载了很多视频,上班看,下班也看,感觉著名大学授课方式与理论水平真不是盖的.一听就上瘾了.所以就想把视频里面的资料再取出来再复习一下,温故而知新.以下本文取自[该如何是好]课程的第一课.我觉得非常精彩. 这是一门讨论公正的课程,我们以一则故事作为引子: 假设你是一名电车司机,你的电车以60km\小时的速度形式在轨道上飞驰,突然发现在轨道的尽头有五名工人在施工,你无法令电车停下来,因为刹车坏了,此时你极度绝望,因为你深知,如果电车撞向那五名工人,他们会全部死亡。假设你对此确信无疑,你极为无助,直到你发现在轨道的右侧还有一条侧轨,而在侧轨的尽头,只有一名工人在那里施工,而你的方向盘并没有坏,只要你想,就可以把电车转到侧轨上去,牺牲一个人而挽救五个人. 下面是我们的第一个问题:何为正确的选择?换了你会怎么做?我们来做个调查,有多少人会把电车开到侧轨上去?有多少人会让电车继续往前开?选择往前开的,请不要把手放下. 测试结果表明:只有少数人选择继续开下去,而大部分人都选择转弯。我们先来听听大家的想法,探究一下原因?你们会认为这是正确的选择。先从大多数选择了转向侧轨的同学开始,为何要这样选择?理由是什么?有没有自告奋勇的. 学生A:我认为当可以只牺牲一个人时,牺牲五个人是不正确的选择。 教授:当可以只牺牲一个人时,牺牲五个人是不正确的选择,这理由不错,还有其他理由吗?人人都赞成这个理由吗? 学生B:我认为这和9.11的时候是一种情况,那些让飞机在宾州坠毁的人,被视为英雄,因为他们选择牺牲了自己,而不是让飞机撞向大楼牺牲更多的人。 教授:这么看来这条原则和9.11是一样的,虽然是悲剧,但牺牲一个人保全五个人依然是更正确的选择。这就是大多数人选择把电车开到侧轨上去的理由吗?现在我们来听听少数派的意见。那些人选择不转弯的. 学生C:我认为这与种族灭绝和极权主义正名是同一种思维,为了一个种族生存下来,以灭绝另一个种族为代价。 教授:那换了是你在这种情况下会怎么做?为了避免骇人听闻的种族灭绝,你打算直接开上去把这五个人撞死吗? 学生C:大概会吧。 教授:我们来考虑一下另一种情况下的例子,看看你们大多数人会不会坚持刚才的原则(即牺牲一个人保全五个人是更好的选择),这次你不是电车司机,只是一名旁观者,你站在桥上俯瞰电车轨道,电车沿轨道从远处驶来,轨道尽头有五名工人,电车刹车坏了,这五名工人将被撞死,但你不是电车司机,你真的爱莫能助,但是你真得不是电车司机,直到你发现,在你的旁边靠着桥站着一个超级大胖子,你可以选择推他一把,他就会摔下桥,正好摔在轨道上挡住电车,他必死无疑,但是可以拯救五个人的生命。 现在,有多少人愿意选择把胖子推下去?有多少人不会?通过举手调查结果,大多数人没有选择推胖子下去,一个显而易见的问题出现了我们“牺牲一个人保全五个人”的这条原则,到底出了什么问题?第一种情况的时候,大多数人会赞成的这条原则怎么了,两种情况下你们都属于多数派,你们是怎么想的?应该如何来解释这两种情况的区别? 学生D:我认为第二种情况牵涉到主动选择推人,而被推的这个人本来和这件事情一点关

哈佛大学公开课观后感

哈佛大学公开课观后感 幸福是我们的终生目标,成功只是幸福的手段。我国在改革开放近30年来,社会在创造了巨大财富的同时,也使得人民生活水平得以进一步的提高,可是,令人疑惑的是,随着物质生活的改善人们的幸福感却没有得以改善,更没有呈现增长态势。现代社会,社会各阶层贫富差距增大,除了金钱和权力外,似乎人们什么都不崇拜,人人都在追求以物质上的富裕为代表的成功。然而,我们要知道,幸福并不是提倡你清心寡欲、也否认追求物质上的充裕与稳定,关键的问和积累,那财富终将变成人们获得幸福的障碍。题是这种所谓的成功只是我们自身提升幸福感的手段和途径,一旦只注重物质财富的获得. 建议: 与朋友共处、聊天。 正确处理学习休息娱乐的关系,适度休息。 感恩。 早上起来看了哈佛大学幸福公开课第5课,最近每天早起就看,希望积极心理学能在我的人生中起到干杆原理的作用,通过这个积极心理学能将我的人生轨道朝良好的循环模式发展。 有几个观点给了我震撼,一个是说思维里的狭窄通道,举了个例子就是到我们遇见老虎时,这个时候狭窄通道会帮

助我们逃离危险,但是到我们思恋的时候,如果还是在这个狭窄通道,就会在思念-悲伤中循环无法走出,扩展模式是非常有用的。第二个观点是引用了甘地的一个例子和一句话。Be the change you want zhe world will be for example.并自己动手做了个小实验。People do what you do, people do not what you say。第三个是情境、环境对人的影响真的非常巨大。有一些很强大的心理暗示在潜意识里起作用,举了人类4分钟跑完一mile这个例子,以及许多心理学家做的实验,人们对权威、对环境的屈服,就是从众力量的巨大作用。但是没有提到如何去克服这些环境对自己的不利影响,所以目前我能做的就是尽量原理这些不利环境,尽量将自己放在有利的积极的环境中。正如人的身体免疫力,也许我们应该加强我们的心理免疫力,正如这位老师说的,加强了我们的心理免疫力我们才能在这个dirty world发挥作用,而不是躲在温室和象牙塔里。第四是自私和道德不是一样的概念,我们总认为快乐是自私的,会自责。他提到了这是个正游戏的概念,就是我的快乐不会让别人的快乐减少,相反快乐是可以传染的,并且说快乐是人的最高追求。当然不是盲目乐观,而是脚踏实地的乐观。并且提出任何理论都应该apply到我们的学习和生活中,让他works up。 当然这些理论并不是放之四海而皆准的,比如说快乐可以传染,但是对于某些嫉妒心强的人,看到别人好自己不开

幸福课_ 哈佛公开课_中英文对照 第一课 校对版

第一课 Hi, good morning. It’s wonderful to be back here. 各位,早上好。很高兴能回到这里。 Wonderful to see you here. 高兴见到你们。 I am teaching this class because I wish a class like this had been taught when I was sitting in your seat as an undergraduate here. 我教授这门课是因为在我读本科阶段时非常希望能学习这样一门课程。 This does not mean it is a class you wish to be taught nor does it mean that it is the right class for you. 可能这门课并不是你希望的那样也可能并不适合你。 But I hope to doing the next couple of lectures is giving you an idea what this class is about so that you can decide whether or not it is for you. 但希望几堂课后,你能有个大概印象让你决定这门课程是否适合你。 I came here in 1992 and studied the computer science and concentrator. 我1992年来到哈佛求学,一开始主修计算机科学。 And when I had I mini epiphany half way through my sophomore year. 大二期间,突然顿悟了。 I realized that I was in a wonderful place with wonderful students around me, wonderful teachers. 我意识到我身处让人神往大学校园周围都是出色的同学,优秀的导师。 I was doing well academically. I was doing well in athletics. I was playing squash at that time. I was doing well socially. 我成绩优异。擅长体育运动。那时壁垒打的不错。社交也游刃有余。 Everything was going well except for the fact that I was unhappy. And I didn’t understand why. 一切都很顺利除了一点我不快乐。而且我不明白为什么。 It was then in a matter of moments that I decided that I had to find out why and become happier. 也就是在那时我决定要找出原因变得快乐。 And that was when I switched my concentration from computer science to philosophy and psychology. 于是我将研究方向从计算机科学转向了哲学及心理学。 With a single question: How can I become happier. 目标只有一个:怎么让自己开心起来。 Overtime I did become happier what contributed most to my happiness was when I encountered a new emerging field that time didn’t have the name that it has today. 渐渐的,我的确变得更快乐了主要是因为我接触了一个新的领域,那时并未正式命名。 But essentially research that falls under or within the field of positive psychology. 但本质上属于积极心理学范畴。 Positive psychology, studying it and applying the ideas to my life has made me significantly happier . 研究积极心理学把其理念应用到生活中让我无比快乐。 It continues to make me happier. 而且这种快乐继续着。

哈佛大学:幸福课(全23集,115盘下载)

哈佛大学:幸福课13(1).mp4 https://www.wendangku.net/doc/b615100561.html,/file/e6rtxoa1# 哈佛大学:幸福课22.mp4 https://www.wendangku.net/doc/b615100561.html,/file/e6rtxosv# 哈佛大学:幸福课21.mp4 https://www.wendangku.net/doc/b615100561.html,/file/dn9mu7pm# 哈佛大学:幸福课20.mp4 https://www.wendangku.net/doc/b615100561.html,/file/e6rtxq0b# 哈佛大学:幸福课19.mp4 https://www.wendangku.net/doc/b615100561.html,/file/dn9mu5yc# 哈佛大学:幸福课18.mp4 https://www.wendangku.net/doc/b615100561.html,/file/bh0gvlvl# 哈佛大学:幸福课17.mp4 https://www.wendangku.net/doc/b615100561.html,/file/clo36msl# 哈佛大学:幸福课16.mp4 https://www.wendangku.net/doc/b615100561.html,/file/e6rtxhp1# 哈佛大学:幸福课15.mp4 https://www.wendangku.net/doc/b615100561.html,/file/bh0gv89g# 哈佛大学:幸福课13.mp4 https://www.wendangku.net/doc/b615100561.html,/file/dn9mtmc7# 哈佛大学:幸福课14.mp4 https://www.wendangku.net/doc/b615100561.html,/file/clo350ja# 哈佛大学:幸福课11.mp4 https://www.wendangku.net/doc/b615100561.html,/file/aqaul593# 哈佛大学:幸福课12.mp4 https://www.wendangku.net/doc/b615100561.html,/file/e6rt9g6e# 哈佛大学:幸福课08.mp4 https://www.wendangku.net/doc/b615100561.html,/file/e6rt9acf# 哈佛大学:幸福课09.mp4

哈佛大学:幸福课04.mp4 https://www.wendangku.net/doc/b615100561.html,/file/bh0goy8n# 哈佛大学:幸福课07.mp4 https://www.wendangku.net/doc/b615100561.html,/file/bh0gouxf# 哈佛大学:幸福课06.mp4 https://www.wendangku.net/doc/b615100561.html,/file/dn9mtgkm# 哈佛大学:幸福课05.mp4 https://www.wendangku.net/doc/b615100561.html,/file/bh0go0d2# 哈佛大学:幸福课03.mp4 https://www.wendangku.net/doc/b615100561.html,/file/clo35txn# 哈佛大学:幸福课02.mp4 https://www.wendangku.net/doc/b615100561.html,/file/clo35qv4# 哈佛大学:幸福课01.mp4 https://www.wendangku.net/doc/b615100561.html,/file/clo35gmc# 哈佛大学:幸福课.mp4

(完整word版)哈佛大学公开课《公平与正义》第2集中英文字幕

Funding for this program is provided by: 本节目的赞助来自... ... Additional funding provided by: 另外的赞助来自... ... Last time, we argued about 上次,我们谈到 the case of The Queen v. Dudley & Stephens, 女王诉Dudley和Stephens案件, the lifeboat case, the case of cannibalism at sea. 那个救生艇上,海上吃人的案件. And with the arguments about the lifeboat in mind, 带着针对这个案件所展开的一些讨论 the arguments for and against what Dudley and Stephens did in mind, 带着支持和反对Dudley和Stephens所做的吃人行为的讨论, let's turn back to the philosophy, the utilitarian philosophy of Jeremy Bentham. 让我们回头来看看Bentham的功利主义哲学. Bentham was born in England in 1748. At the age of 12, he went to Oxford. Bentham于1748年出生于英国.12岁那年,他去了牛津大学. At 15, he went to law school. He was admitted to the Bar at age 19 15岁时,他去了法学院.19岁就取得了律师资格 but he never practiced law. 但他没有从事于律师行业. Instead, he devoted his life to jurisprudence and moral philosophy.

哈佛公开课《幸福课》(积极心理学)有关笔记(无顺序)

哈佛公开课《幸福课》(积极心理学)有 关笔记(无顺序) 话题:适应力现实教育学习 一、这个世界需要具有实践精神的理想主义者。据调查,成功的大学生具有强烈的使命感,想做伟大的事,让世界变得更美好。“我该怎样使这个世界变得更好?”这不是空话,无论在学术还是实践工作中,他们勇往直前,做到了了不起的事,充满热情的理想主义者,特别善良。有些人只是“自我”的一代,这一代人所关心的一切只是“我要多赚点钱”,“我要买套更大的房子”,“我要变得成功,取得更多赞誉”,“变得更有威望”。但有这种想法的人,他们的错误在于,他们只看到了这些。他们也不如有崇高使命感的人成功。二、有时,光有美好愿望,我们还是无法发挥全部潜能,甚至有些情况下造成的伤害多于帮助。理想主义远远不够,往往使对方陷入被动受害者地位,而不是帮助产生积极的主导心态。(皮格马利翁)赞扬别人,赞扬小孩,是有害的。如果没有分辨地夸奖别人,从长远角度讲,实际上害人比帮助人更多,无论是身心健康还是成功等方面。三、“如果我们对自身的培养

不够,对各种人际关系培养不够,就会发生个人成长失败。” 四、心理学家证实了培养乐观精神能预防儿童和成人的抑郁和焦虑,约能将他们两年内患病率减半。人类有些因素可以抵制精神疾病:勇气、面向未来、乐观、人际技巧、信仰、职业道德、希望、诚实、毅力、心胸和洞察力等。培养自身优势、培养能力、关注健康、信仰、乐观、自信等等,能更好面对生活困难。四、冥想可以极大程度上改变我们的大脑,可以帮助产生积极的情绪,而在痛苦面前变得更坚定。每周三次锻炼,每次三十分钟,效果与现有最有效的心理药物是一样的。五、相信改变是可能的。当内部(大脑的想法)与外部(现实)不一致时,我们会感觉不舒服。改变的方法:1、更新基模2、忽略外部信息3、主动寻找证据4、创造新的现实。运动员跑跑,开始都不相信4分钟跑完1公里,直到一人提出可以,并且做到,之后很快很多人都可以做到。 六、学会失败,从失败中学习。史上最成功的人,通常也是失败最多的人。(爱迪生发明灯泡)七、成功别无他法,成功没有捷径。八、悲观者:短期目标、长期目标都很现实。乐观者:短期目标不现实,长期目标现实。因为乐观者的短期目标总是很乐观,如第一个提出可以4分钟跑完1公里的人。但最后他实现了,所以,长期目标就成了现实。八、高的期望导致失望。越战战俘,生存者有两个特点:1、相信能重获自由。2、看中现实,正确估计形势,正视残酷现实。

哈佛大学公开课justice整理版

This is a course about justice and we begin with a story. 这是一堂关于公平与正义的公共课,让我们先从一个故事讲起 Suppose you’re the driver of a trolley car, and your trolley car is hurtling down the track at 60 miles an hour. 假设你现在是一辆有轨电车的司机而你的电车正在铁轨上以时 速60英里疾驶 And at the end of the track you notice five workers working on the track. 在铁轨末端, 你发现有五个工人在铁轨上工作 You try to stop but you can't, your brakes don’t work. 你尽力想停下电车, 但是你做不到,电车的刹车失灵了 You feel desperate because you know that if you crash into these five workers, they will all die. 你觉得十分绝望,因为你知道如果你就这样撞向这5个工人,他们必死无疑 Let’s assume you know that for sure. 假定你很清楚这一点

And so you feel helpless until you notice that there is, off to the right, a side track and at the end of that track, there is one worker, working on the track. 正当你感到无助的时候, 你突然发现就在右边一条岔道,那根 轨道的尽头只有一个工人在那里工作 Your steering wheel works, so you can turn the trolley car, if you want to, onto the side track killing the one but sparing the five. 你的方向盘没有失灵, 只要你愿意你可以让电车转向到那条分 叉铁轨上撞死一个工人但却因此救了另外5个人 Here’s our first question: what’s the ri ght thing to do? 现在提出第一个问题,我们该怎么做才对? What would you do? Let’s take a poll. 你会怎么做? 我们做个调查看看 How many would turn the trolley car onto the side track? Raise your hands. 有多少人会选择让电车转向到分叉铁轨上,请举手 How many wouldn’t? How many would go straight ahead? 多少人不会?多少人选择就这样笔直开下去?

哈佛公开课 幸福 第一课 中英文对照字幕整理

Hi, good morning. It’s wonderful to be back here.各位,早上好。很高兴能回到这里。 Wonderful to see you here.高兴见到你们。 I am teaching this class because I wish a class like this had been taught when I was sitting in your seat as an undergraduate here.我教授这门课是因为在我读本科阶段时非常希望能学习这样一门课程。 This does not mean it is a class you wish to be taught nor does it mean that it is the right class for you.可能这门课并不是你希望的那样也可能并不适合你。 But I hope to doing the next couple of lectures is giving you an idea what this class is about so that you can decide whether or not it is for you.但希望几堂课后,你能有个大概印象让你决定这门课程是否适合你。 I came here in 1992 and studied the computer science and concentrator.我1992年来到哈佛求学,一开始主修计算机科学。 And when I had I mini epiphany half way through my sophomore year.大二期间,突然顿悟了。 I realized that I was in a wonderful place with wonderful students around me, wonderful teachers.我意识到我身处让人神往大学校园周围都是出色的同学,优秀的导师。 I was doing well academically. I was doing well in athletics. I was playing squash at that time. I was doing well socially.我成绩优异。擅长体育运动。那时壁垒打的不错。社交也游刃有余。 Everything was going well except for the fact that I was unhappy. And I didn’t understand why.一切都很顺利除了一点我不快乐。而且我不明白为什么。 It was then in a matter of moments that I decided that I had to find out why and become happier.也就是在那时我决定要找出原因变得快乐。 And that was when I switched my concentration from computer science to philosophy and psychology.于是我将研究方向从计算机科学转向了哲学及心理学。 With a single question: How can I become happier.目标只有一个:怎么让自己开心起来。 Overtime I did become happier what contributed most to my happiness was when I en countered a new emerging field that time didn’t have the name that it has today.渐渐的,我的确变得更快乐了主要是因为我接触了一个新的领域,那时并未正式命名。 But essentially research that falls under or within the field of positive psychology.但本质上属于积极心理学范畴。

相关文档
相关文档 最新文档